友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!
读书室 返回本书目录 加入书签 我的书架 我的书签 TXT全本下载 『收藏到我的浏览器』

posterior analytics-第13部分

快捷操作: 按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页 按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页 按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部! 如果本书没有阅读完,想下次继续接着阅读,可使用上方 "收藏到我的浏览器" 功能 和 "加入书签" 功能!




as we have exemplified; it follows that in the case of the other



causes also full knowledge is attained when an attribute no longer



inheres because of something else。 Thus; when we learn that exterior



angles are equal to four right angles because they are the exterior



angles of an isosceles; there still remains the question 'Why has



isosceles this attribute?' and its answer 'Because it is a triangle;



and a triangle has it because a triangle is a rectilinear figure。'



If rectilinear figure possesses the property for no further reason; at



this point we have full knowledge…but at this point our knowledge



has become commensurately universal; and so we conclude that



commensurately universal demonstration is superior。



  (6) The more demonstration becomes particular the more it sinks into



an indeterminate manifold; while universal demonstration tends to



the simple and determinate。 But objects so far as they are an



indeterminate manifold are unintelligible; so far as they are



determinate; intelligible: they are therefore intelligible rather in



so far as they are universal than in so far as they are particular。



From this it follows that universals are more demonstrable: but



since relative and correlative increase concomitantly; of the more



demonstrable there will be fuller demonstration。 Hence the



commensurate and universal form; being more truly demonstration; is



the superior。



  (7) Demonstration which teaches two things is preferable to



demonstration which teaches only one。 He who possesses



commensurately universal demonstration knows the particular as well;



but he who possesses particular demonstration does not know the



universal。 So that this is an additional reason for preferring



commensurately universal demonstration。 And there is yet this



further argument:



  (8) Proof becomes more and more proof of the commensurate



universal as its middle term approaches nearer to the basic truth; and



nothing is so near as the immediate premiss which is itself the



basic truth。 If; then; proof from the basic truth is more accurate



than proof not so derived; demonstration which depends more closely on



it is more accurate than demonstration which is less closely



dependent。 But commensurately universal demonstration is characterized



by this closer dependence; and is therefore superior。 Thus; if A had



to be proved to inhere in D; and the middles were B and C; B being the



higher term would render the demonstration which it mediated the



more universal。



  Some of these arguments; however; are dialectical。 The clearest



indication of the precedence of commensurately universal demonstration



is as follows: if of two propositions; a prior and a posterior; we



have a grasp of the prior; we have a kind of knowledge…a potential



grasp…of the posterior as well。 For example; if one knows that the



angles of all triangles are equal to two right angles; one knows in



a sense…potentially…that the isosceles' angles also are equal to two



right angles; even if one does not know that the isosceles is a



triangle; but to grasp this posterior proposition is by no means to



know the commensurate universal either potentially or actually。



Moreover; commensurately universal demonstration is through and



through intelligible; particular demonstration issues in



sense…perception。







                                25







  The preceding arguments constitute our defence of the superiority of



commensurately universal to particular demonstration。 That affirmative



demonstration excels negative may be shown as follows。



  (1) We may assume the superiority ceteris paribus of the



demonstration which derives from fewer postulates or hypotheses…in



short from fewer premisses; for; given that all these are equally well



known; where they are fewer knowledge will be more speedily



acquired; and that is a desideratum。 The argument implied in our



contention that demonstration from fewer assumptions is superior may



be set out in universal form as follows。 Assuming that in both cases



alike the middle terms are known; and that middles which are prior are



better known than such as are posterior; we may suppose two



demonstrations of the inherence of A in E; the one proving it



through the middles B; C and D; the other through F and G。 Then A…D is



known to the same degree as A…E (in the second proof); but A…D is



better known than and prior to A…E (in the first proof); since A…E



is proved through A…D; and the ground is more certain than the



conclusion。



  Hence demonstration by fewer premisses is ceteris paribus



superior。 Now both affirmative and negative demonstration operate



through three terms and two premisses; but whereas the former



assumes only that something is; the latter assumes both that something



is and that something else is not; and thus operating through more



kinds of premiss is inferior。



  (2) It has been proved that no conclusion follows if both



premisses are negative; but that one must be negative; the other



affirmative。 So we are compelled to lay down the following



additional rule: as the demonstration expands; the affirmative



premisses must increase in number; but there cannot be more than one



negative premiss in each complete proof。 Thus; suppose no B is A;



and all C is B。 Then if both the premisses are to be again expanded; a



middle must be interposed。 Let us interpose D between A and B; and E



between B and C。 Then clearly E is affirmatively related to B and C;



while D is affirmatively related to B but negatively to A; for all B



is D; but there must be no D which is A。 Thus there proves to be a



single negative premiss; A…D。 In the further prosyllogisms too it is



the same; because in the terms of an affirmative syllogism the



middle is always related affirmatively to both extremes; in a negative



syllogism it must be negatively related only to one of them; and so



this negation comes to be a single negative premiss; the other



premisses being affirmative。 If; then; that through which a truth is



proved is a better known and more certain truth; and if the negative



proposition is proved through the affirmative and not vice versa;



affirmative demonstration; being prior and better known and more



certain; will be superior。



  (3) The basic truth of demonstrative syllogism is the universal



immediate premiss; and the universal premiss asserts in affirmative



demonstration and in negative denies: and the affirmative



proposition is prior to and better known than the negative (since



affirmation explains denial and is prior to denial; just as being is



prior to not…being)。 It follows that the basic premiss of



affirmative demonstration is superior to that of negative



demonstration; and the demonstration which uses superior basic



premisses is superior。



  (4) Affirmative demonstration is more of the nature of a basic



form of proof; because it is a sine qua non of negative demonstration。







                                26







  Since affirmative demonstration is superior to negative; it is



clearly superior also to reductio ad impossibile。 We must first make



certain what is the difference between negative demonstration and



reductio ad impossibile。 Let us suppose that no B is A; and that all C



is B: the conclusion necessarily follows that no C is A。 If these



premisses are assumed; therefore; the negative demonstration that no C



is A is direct。 Reductio ad impossibile; on the other hand; proceeds



as follows。 Supposing we are to prove that does not inhere in B; we



have to assume that it does inhere; and further that B inheres in C;



with the resulting inference that A inheres in C。 This we have to



suppose a known and admitted impossibility; and we then infer that A



cannot inhere in B。 Thus if the inherence of B in C is not questioned;



A's inherence in B is impossible。



  The order of the terms is the same in both proofs: they differ



according to which of the negative propositions is the better known;



the one denying A of B or the one denying A of C。 When the falsity



of the conclusion is the better known; we use reductio ad



impossible; when the major premiss of the syllogism is the more



obvious; we use direct demonstration。 All the same the proposition



denying A of B is; in the order of being; prior to that denying A of



C; for premisses are prior to the conclusion which follows from



them; and 'no C is A' is the conclusion; 'no B is A' one of its



premisses。 For the destructive result of reductio
返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0
快捷操作: 按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页 按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页 按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!