友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!
posterior analytics-第7部分
快捷操作: 按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页 按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页 按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部! 如果本书没有阅读完,想下次继续接着阅读,可使用上方 "收藏到我的浏览器" 功能 和 "加入书签" 功能!
arguments formally illogical do sometimes occur through taking as
middles mere attributes of the major and minor terms。 An instance of
this is Caeneus' proof that fire increases in geometrical
proportion: 'Fire'; he argues; 'increases rapidly; and so does
geometrical proportion'。 There is no syllogism so; but there is a
syllogism if the most rapidly increasing proportion is geometrical and
the most rapidly increasing proportion is attributable to fire in
its motion。 Sometimes; no doubt; it is impossible to reason from
premisses predicating mere attributes: but sometimes it is possible;
though the possibility is overlooked。 If false premisses could never
give true conclusions 'resolution' would be easy; for premisses and
conclusion would in that case inevitably reciprocate。 I might then
argue thus: let A be an existing fact; let the existence of A imply
such and such facts actually known to me to exist; which we may call
B。 I can now; since they reciprocate; infer A from B。
Reciprocation of premisses and conclusion is more frequent in
mathematics; because mathematics takes definitions; but never an
accident; for its premisses…a second characteristic distinguishing
mathematical reasoning from dialectical disputations。
A science expands not by the interposition of fresh middle terms;
but by the apposition of fresh extreme terms。 E。g。 A is predicated
of B; B of C; C of D; and so indefinitely。 Or the expansion may be
lateral: e。g。 one major A; may be proved of two minors; C and E。
Thus let A represent number…a number or number taken
indeterminately; B determinate odd number; C any particular odd
number。 We can then predicate A of C。 Next let D represent determinate
even number; and E even number。 Then A is predicable of E。
13
Knowledge of the fact differs from knowledge of the reasoned fact。
To begin with; they differ within the same science and in two ways:
(1) when the premisses of the syllogism are not immediate (for then
the proximate cause is not contained in them…a necessary condition
of knowledge of the reasoned fact): (2) when the premisses are
immediate; but instead of the cause the better known of the two
reciprocals is taken as the middle; for of two reciprocally predicable
terms the one which is not the cause may quite easily be the better
known and so become the middle term of the demonstration。 Thus (2) (a)
you might prove as follows that the planets are near because they do
not twinkle: let C be the planets; B not twinkling; A proximity。
Then B is predicable of C; for the planets do not twinkle。 But A is
also predicable of B; since that which does not twinkle is nearwe
must take this truth as having been reached by induction or
sense…perception。 Therefore A is a necessary predicate of C; so that
we have demonstrated that the planets are near。 This syllogism;
then; proves not the reasoned fact but only the fact; since they are
not near because they do not twinkle; but; because they are near; do
not twinkle。 The major and middle of the proof; however; may be
reversed; and then the demonstration will be of the reasoned fact。
Thus: let C be the planets; B proximity; A not twinkling。 Then B is an
attribute of C; and A…not twinkling…of B。 Consequently A is predicable
of C; and the syllogism proves the reasoned fact; since its middle
term is the proximate cause。 Another example is the inference that the
moon is spherical from its manner of waxing。 Thus: since that which so
waxes is spherical; and since the moon so waxes; clearly the moon is
spherical。 Put in this form; the syllogism turns out to be proof of
the fact; but if the middle and major be reversed it is proof of the
reasoned fact; since the moon is not spherical because it waxes in a
certain manner; but waxes in such a manner because it is spherical。
(Let C be the moon; B spherical; and A waxing。) Again (b); in cases
where the cause and the effect are not reciprocal and the effect is
the better known; the fact is demonstrated but not the reasoned
fact。 This also occurs (1) when the middle falls outside the major and
minor; for here too the strict cause is not given; and so the
demonstration is of the fact; not of the reasoned fact。 For example;
the question 'Why does not a wall breathe?' might be answered;
'Because it is not an animal'; but that answer would not give the
strict cause; because if not being an animal causes the absence of
respiration; then being an animal should be the cause of
respiration; according to the rule that if the negation of causes
the non…inherence of y; the affirmation of x causes the inherence of
y; e。g。 if the disproportion of the hot and cold elements is the cause
of ill health; their proportion is the cause of health; and
conversely; if the assertion of x causes the inherence of y; the
negation of x must cause y's non…inherence。 But in the case given this
consequence does not result; for not every animal breathes。 A
syllogism with this kind of cause takes place in the second figure。
Thus: let A be animal; B respiration; C wall。 Then A is predicable
of all B (for all that breathes is animal); but of no C; and
consequently B is predicable of no C; that is; the wall does not
breathe。 Such causes are like far…fetched explanations; which
precisely consist in making the cause too remote; as in Anacharsis'
account of why the Scythians have no flute…players; namely because
they have no vines。
Thus; then; do the syllogism of the fact and the syllogism of the
reasoned fact differ within one science and according to the
position of the middle terms。 But there is another way too in which
the fact and the reasoned fact differ; and that is when they are
investigated respectively by different sciences。 This occurs in the
case of problems related to one another as subordinate and superior;
as when optical problems are subordinated to geometry; mechanical
problems to stereometry; harmonic problems to arithmetic; the data
of observation to astronomy。 (Some of these sciences bear almost the
same name; e。g。 mathematical and nautical astronomy; mathematical
and acoustical harmonics。) Here it is the business of the empirical
observers to know the fact; of the mathematicians to know the reasoned
fact; for the latter are in possession of the demonstrations giving
the causes; and are often ignorant of the fact: just as we have
often a clear insight into a universal; but through lack of
observation are ignorant of some of its particular instances。 These
connexions have a perceptible existence though they are manifestations
of forms。 For the mathematical sciences concern forms: they do not
demonstrate properties of a substratum; since; even though the
geometrical subjects are predicable as properties of a perceptible
substratum; it is not as thus predicable that the mathematician
demonstrates properties of them。 As optics is related to geometry;
so another science is related to optics; namely the theory of the
rainbow。 Here knowledge of the fact is within the province of the
natural philosopher; knowledge of the reasoned fact within that of the
optician; either qua optician or qua mathematical optician。 Many
sciences not standing in this mutual relation enter into it at points;
e。g。 medicine and geometry: it is the physician's business to know
that circular wounds heal more slowly; the geometer's to know the
reason why。
14
Of all the figures the most scientific is the first。 Thus; it is the
vehicle of the demonstrations of all the mathematical sciences; such
as arithmetic; geometry; and optics; and practically all of all
sciences that investigate causes: for the syllogism of the reasoned
fact is either exclusively or generally speaking and in most cases
in this figure…a second proof that this figure is the most scientific;
for grasp of a reasoned conclusion is the primary condition of
knowledge。 Thirdly; the first is the only figure which enables us to
pursue knowledge of the essence of a thing。 In the second figure no
affirmative conclusion is possible; and knowledge of a thing's essence
must be affirmative; while in the third figure the conclusion can be
affirmative; but cannot be universal; and essence must have a
universal character: e。g。 man is not two…footed animal in any
qualified sense; but universally。 Finally; the first figure has no
need of the others; while it is by means
快捷操作: 按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页 按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页 按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!